The theory of voluntary parental obligations holds that parents acquire obligations to their children by volunteering for those obligations. The claim is that only those who voluntarily accept the responsibility for parenting a child are obliged to do so, and only from the point that they accept this role onwards, and only unless or until they give it up for adoption. The justification made for this theory is based on claims about how adoptive parents gain obligations. The line of argument runs as follows:
- Adoptive parents become parents by voluntary agreement.
- Adoptive parents have the same obligations as biological parents.
- Any parent (biological or adoptive) may legitimately divest themselves of enforceable parental obligation voluntarily by putting up their child for adoption.
- Therefore all parental obligations arise from voluntary agreement.
As will be argued in this article, every premise in this line of argument is false, and the conclusion is false too.
1. It Is Not Voluntary Agreement That Obligates Adoptive Parents
The argument that adopters have positive obligations implies that adopted children have an enforceable claim against their adopters. How can this claim arise? It cannot be as a result of contract, since children cannot contract. One might argue over exactly when young adults may be able to consent to their own adoption, but there is no way a young child can be said to consent to being adopted.
Also, any agreement to adoption between the biological parents and the adopters is irrelevant since it cannot explain how the child has a claim on the adopter. It is the child that has the claim and the child cannot consent. The fact that the biological parents and adopters have both consented does not change that.
If the child does have a claim on the adopter, it can only be as a result of tort. A tort claim arises independently of consent or contract. A tort could impose obligations on the adopter as a result of the actions of the adopter. What actions could those be?
The only way that an adopter could have positive obligations to a child is through the adopter being responsible for a child being in a state of peril. As I have argued elsewhere, an adoptive parent effectively removes the child from the obligated caregiver in the child's life, which is the creation of a state of peril, and this gives the adoptive parent a positive obligation to act as the new caregiver.
Even if the biological parents were not fulfilling all their obligations, the adoptive parents are still effectively cutting off any chance that the child has of receiving care from the biological parent. This is the creation of peril, and it is mitigated by the adoptive parent meeting the obligations instead.
Finding an abandoned child and giving it shelter does not create an enforceable parental obligation on the rescuer from the child. Although a rescuer does not acquire parental obligations the minute he saves an abandoned baby, he is temporarily obliged to look after the child whilst in possession of it, and to pass on the child responsibly. This is because a rescuer is effectively precluding the child from anyone else's care in that time and is therefore temporarily responsible for relieving the child's peril during that time. The same temporary obligations apply to foster parents.
Formal adoption differs from rescue or fostering because it entails the exclusion of anyone else from parenting the child. Because of this, formal adoption creates enforceable parental obligations because the adopter is permanently excluding anyone else from caring for the child.
If you tell others not to attempt saving a non-swimmer who has fallen in to a pool because you intend to be the saviour, then you are responsible for relieving that non-swimmer from peril. Having prevented the non-swimmer from benefitting from any other saviour, you now have a responsibility to follow through otherwise you would cause the resultant drowning via creation of peril.
2. Adoptive Parents Do Not Have Exactly the Same Obligations as Biological Parents
The fact that biological parents and adoptive parents both have obligations does not prove that obligations are voluntary. It does not follow that biological parents acquire their obligations voluntarily because adopters volunteer for their role. On the contrary, as argued above, it is the other way around. Adoptive parents acquire obligations in a similar way to biological parents: by tort as a consequence of actions that result in creation of peril (albeit through different circumstances).
The premise that biological parents have exactly the same obligations as adoptive parents is merely an assertion and is not accurate. As I have argued in another post, a biological parent who gives up their child has not legitimately lost their obligation, but rather they have effectively instructed an agent to fulfil the obligation on their behalf. If the adopter failed to fulfil obligations on behalf of the biological parent, the child would arguably still have an enforceable claim against the original parent. In this way a biological parent always has a residual obligation that could be called upon, whereas an adopter has the obligations of a kind of agent. The two are not the same.
3. No Parent Can Legitimately Divest Themselves of Parental Obligations
The fact that the institution of adoption exists is not proof that parental obligation is legitimately optional. As I have argued elsewhere, parents cannot legitimately absolve themselves of their obligation solely by passing on responsibility to an adopter, because a parent's obligation is to the child.. However, if parents are not living up to their obligations, the first concern is the interest of the child.
Accepting the institution of adoption recognises that a bad situation is preferable to a catastrophic situation. If someone fails to comply with their obligations, it is better that they do so in a way that can be mitigated than if they do so in a way that leads to disaster.
It is not legitimate for the pilot of a passenger plane to choose to parachute out mid-flight, but I would still much rather that he made arrangements with someone to take over the plane safely than if he just let go of the controls, parachuted out, and let the aircraft plummet to the ground.
There is no contradiction between the argument that it is in the best interests of children for adoption to be legal and the argument that it is not morally legitimate for parents to give their children up for adoption. Rather, the rationale is simply that in cases where parental obligations are unenforceable, the interests of the children take priority over other considerations.
4. Parental Obligations Arise From Action Not Agreement
The theory of voluntary parental obligations is riddled with problems:
- Since children cannot contract, it relies on an imaginary social contract between parents and every other adult.
- It cannot hold men responsible for any children that they father.
- It cannot explain why the act of volunteering for obligations gives someone legitimate authority over any particular child.
- Lastly, as has been discussed in this post, it is based on an argument from adoption which is false.
The theory of voluntary obligations is wrong because parental obligations are not voluntary. They are the result of causal action. Parents are those who engage in actions that can cause the creation of a child in a state of peril. Parents are responsible for the state of peril and therefore have an obligation by tort to remove the peril.
Adoptive parents also acquire positive obligations through actions that result in creation of peril: adopters exclude a child from their legitimate claim on their biological parents.
But adoption is not exactly the same as biological parenthood. It is complicated by the fact that biological parents never legitimately lose their obligations, which implies that biological parents are always residually obliged, even when they have given up their children to adopters.
Adoption is a kind of damage control. It is a way of making the best of a bad situation. It does not prove the argument that parental obligations are voluntary.